Exercise 3.6.4
Prove Proposition 3.6.14.
Proposition 3.6.14 contains six proposals so let's look at each as we develop solutions to each.
(a) Let be a finite set, and let be an object which is not an element of . Then is finite and .
The finite set has a cardinality of , which by Definition 3.6.10 is a natural number. This also means, by Definition 3.6.5, there is a bijection .
Since is not in , the bijection doesn't map to an element of . We can define a new bijection which maps just as for , and maps to , since is not in .
This is a bijection from to . This means has a cardinality , and because this is a natural number (successor to ), it is also a finite set.
(b) Let and be finite sets. Then is finite and . If in addition and are disjoint (i.e., ), then .
There are two cases to consider, and are disjoint, and and are not disjoint.
Let's consider the disjoint case first.
Since both sets are finite, their cardinalities and are natural numbers (Definition 3.6.10). This means there exist bijections (Definition 3.6.5) and . Since the two sets are disjoint, they share no common elements, and so we can define a new bijection . Thus, if and are disjoint, then .
Now consider the non-disjoint case.
Since both sets are finite, their cardinalities and are natural numbers. This means there exist bijections and .
Here and do share at least one common element. That means there exists an that is also in . Therefore, a bijection requires .
To see this more clearly, consider , the set without any elements that are also in . Therefore the cardinality of is . We have and so
Thus, in the general case, .
(c) Let be a finite set, and let be a subset of . Then is finite, and . If in addition (i.e., is a proper subset of ), then we have .
is a finite set so it has a natural number cardinality , and there is a bijection .
If is a subset of , then it is finite too. We can define a function with domain and which maps as . Since is a bijection, so is .
This is bijective with , where because the domain of is some or all of . That is, .
In the case is a proper subset of , then there is at least one element of that is not in . And so the domain of is not equal to the domain of . This means is bijective with where now because the domain of is some but not all of . That is, .
(d) If is a finite set, and is a function, then is a finite set with . One has equality if and only if is one-to-one.
The definition of a function requires it to map each element of to a single element of . Furthermore, for each element , there exists an such that .
There are two cases: there could be a unique for each , or there could be more than one element of that maps to .
In the case there is a unique for each , the function is one-to-one, a bijection, and so .
In the case there is more than one element of that map to the same , the function is not one-to-one. In this case there is a bijection between and , where .
Thus in general, .
(e) Let and be finite sets. Then Cartesian product is finite and .
Consider where , and where . Since both sets are finite, and are natural numbers.
The Cartesian product is the set of ordered pairs,
For each of the elements of there are elements of the form in . All of these elements are unique because each element of and is unique.
Therefore, there are elements of , which is . This is a natural number, and so the cartesian product is finite.
(f) Let and be finite sets. Then the set (defined in Axiom 3.11) is finite and .
Let's remind ourselves of Axiom 3.1.1
(Power set axiom). Let and be sets. Then there exists a set, denoted , which consists of all the functions from to .
We'll prove this proposition by induction.
Let be the statement: where .
For the base case , we have , a singleton set. The power set is the set of all functions from to . Since there is only one element of , there are possible functions from to . That is, , and so the base case is true.
Let's now assume is true, and show is true. The statement is where .
If we extend the set with an element it doesn't currently have , we have , and . The addition of one extra element to means that for each of the existing functions , there are an additional new possible functions .
More specifically, each function can be extended to map to any one of elements of .
Thus , and so is true.
We have shown by induction that .
Since and are finite, then , and are natural numbers. This means the cardinality of the power set is also a natural number, and so is finite too.